A Dilemma for Sterba

James Sterba argues that a good God is not logically possible. He argues that what he calls the Pauline Principle, which says that we should never do evil that good may come of it, implies that a good God would prevent horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions. However, there are plenty of exa...

Full description

Bibliographic Details
Main Author: Bruce Russell
Format: Article
Language:English
Published: MDPI AG 2022-08-01
Series:Religions
Subjects:
Online Access:https://www.mdpi.com/2077-1444/13/9/783
_version_ 1797482922758897664
author Bruce Russell
author_facet Bruce Russell
author_sort Bruce Russell
collection DOAJ
description James Sterba argues that a good God is not logically possible. He argues that what he calls the Pauline Principle, which says that we should never do evil that good may come of it, implies that a good God would prevent horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions. However, there are plenty of examples of such actions in our world. So, a good God does not exist. I offer an example from Derek Parfit, and one of my own, that calls the Pauline Principle into question. Sterba believes that what he calls Moral Evil Prevention Requirements (MEPRs) follow from the Pauline Principle, and that they are necessary truths which imply that a good God would prevent horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions. Whether these (MEPRs) follow from the Pauline Principle or do not, they may be necessary truths that could form the basis of Sterba’s argument. However, I argue that they are not necessary truths. If modified to become such, Sterba faces a challenge from the Skeptical Theists that can only be met by turning his argument into an evidential version of the problem of evil. I compare Sterba’s argument with my version of the evidential argument from evil that says that if God exists, there is not excessive, unnecessary suffering and whose second premise says there is. I argue that it is easier to establish that there is excessive, unnecessary suffering than to establish Sterba’s second premise (once his principles are modified). That second premise will say that there are no goods that logically require God to allow immoral actions that have horrendous evil consequences. Sterba faces a dilemma: either he has an unsound logical argument or a weak evidential argument for the non-existence of God. In either case, he does not have a good logical argument for atheism.
first_indexed 2024-03-09T22:40:25Z
format Article
id doaj.art-3948c6a2c2e24d008e3a3b409895a1ff
institution Directory Open Access Journal
issn 2077-1444
language English
last_indexed 2024-03-09T22:40:25Z
publishDate 2022-08-01
publisher MDPI AG
record_format Article
series Religions
spelling doaj.art-3948c6a2c2e24d008e3a3b409895a1ff2023-11-23T18:40:51ZengMDPI AGReligions2077-14442022-08-0113978310.3390/rel13090783A Dilemma for SterbaBruce Russell0Wayne State University, Detroit, MI 48201, USAJames Sterba argues that a good God is not logically possible. He argues that what he calls the Pauline Principle, which says that we should never do evil that good may come of it, implies that a good God would prevent horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions. However, there are plenty of examples of such actions in our world. So, a good God does not exist. I offer an example from Derek Parfit, and one of my own, that calls the Pauline Principle into question. Sterba believes that what he calls Moral Evil Prevention Requirements (MEPRs) follow from the Pauline Principle, and that they are necessary truths which imply that a good God would prevent horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions. Whether these (MEPRs) follow from the Pauline Principle or do not, they may be necessary truths that could form the basis of Sterba’s argument. However, I argue that they are not necessary truths. If modified to become such, Sterba faces a challenge from the Skeptical Theists that can only be met by turning his argument into an evidential version of the problem of evil. I compare Sterba’s argument with my version of the evidential argument from evil that says that if God exists, there is not excessive, unnecessary suffering and whose second premise says there is. I argue that it is easier to establish that there is excessive, unnecessary suffering than to establish Sterba’s second premise (once his principles are modified). That second premise will say that there are no goods that logically require God to allow immoral actions that have horrendous evil consequences. Sterba faces a dilemma: either he has an unsound logical argument or a weak evidential argument for the non-existence of God. In either case, he does not have a good logical argument for atheism.https://www.mdpi.com/2077-1444/13/9/783the problem of evilPauline PrincipleDoctrine of the Double EffectSkeptical TheismMoral Evil Prevention Requirementshorrendous evil consequences of immoral actions
spellingShingle Bruce Russell
A Dilemma for Sterba
Religions
the problem of evil
Pauline Principle
Doctrine of the Double Effect
Skeptical Theism
Moral Evil Prevention Requirements
horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions
title A Dilemma for Sterba
title_full A Dilemma for Sterba
title_fullStr A Dilemma for Sterba
title_full_unstemmed A Dilemma for Sterba
title_short A Dilemma for Sterba
title_sort dilemma for sterba
topic the problem of evil
Pauline Principle
Doctrine of the Double Effect
Skeptical Theism
Moral Evil Prevention Requirements
horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions
url https://www.mdpi.com/2077-1444/13/9/783
work_keys_str_mv AT brucerussell adilemmaforsterba
AT brucerussell dilemmaforsterba