The evolution of morality and the role of commitment

A considerable share of the literature on the evolution of human cooperation considers the question why we have not evolved to play the Nash equilibrium in prisoners’ dilemmas or public goods games. In order to understand human morality and pro-social behaviour, we suggest that it would actually be...

Full description

Bibliographic Details
Main Authors: Aslihan Akdeniz, Matthijs van Veelen
Format: Article
Language:English
Published: Cambridge University Press 2021-01-01
Series:Evolutionary Human Sciences
Subjects:
Online Access:https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/identifier/S2513843X21000360/type/journal_article
_version_ 1811156368944529408
author Aslihan Akdeniz
Matthijs van Veelen
author_facet Aslihan Akdeniz
Matthijs van Veelen
author_sort Aslihan Akdeniz
collection DOAJ
description A considerable share of the literature on the evolution of human cooperation considers the question why we have not evolved to play the Nash equilibrium in prisoners’ dilemmas or public goods games. In order to understand human morality and pro-social behaviour, we suggest that it would actually be more informative to investigate why we have not evolved to play the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium in sequential games, such as the ultimatum game and the trust game. The ‘rationally irrational’ behaviour that can evolve in such games gives a much better match with actual human behaviour, including elements of morality such as honesty, responsibility and sincerity, as well as the more hostile aspects of human nature, such as anger and vengefulness. The mechanism at work here is commitment, which does not need population structure, nor does it need interactions to be repeated. We argue that this shift in focus can not only help explain why humans have evolved to know wrong from right, but also why other animals, with similar population structures and similar rates of repetition, have not evolved similar moral sentiments. The suggestion that the evolutionary function of morality is to help us commit to otherwise irrational behaviour stems from the work of Robert Frank (American Economic Review, 77(4), 593–604, 1987; Passions within reason: The strategic role of the emotions, WW Norton, 1988), which has played a surprisingly modest role in the scientific debate to date.
first_indexed 2024-04-10T04:50:23Z
format Article
id doaj.art-510d896d350d43a4a7020e94eb03572b
institution Directory Open Access Journal
issn 2513-843X
language English
last_indexed 2024-04-10T04:50:23Z
publishDate 2021-01-01
publisher Cambridge University Press
record_format Article
series Evolutionary Human Sciences
spelling doaj.art-510d896d350d43a4a7020e94eb03572b2023-03-09T12:32:19ZengCambridge University PressEvolutionary Human Sciences2513-843X2021-01-01310.1017/ehs.2021.36The evolution of morality and the role of commitmentAslihan Akdeniz0Matthijs van Veelen1https://orcid.org/0000-0002-8290-9212University of Amsterdam, Roetersstraat 11, 1018 WB Amsterdam, The Netherlands Tinbergen Institute, Gustav Mahlerplein 117, 1082 MS Amsterdam, The NetherlandsUniversity of Amsterdam, Roetersstraat 11, 1018 WB Amsterdam, The Netherlands Tinbergen Institute, Gustav Mahlerplein 117, 1082 MS Amsterdam, The NetherlandsA considerable share of the literature on the evolution of human cooperation considers the question why we have not evolved to play the Nash equilibrium in prisoners’ dilemmas or public goods games. In order to understand human morality and pro-social behaviour, we suggest that it would actually be more informative to investigate why we have not evolved to play the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium in sequential games, such as the ultimatum game and the trust game. The ‘rationally irrational’ behaviour that can evolve in such games gives a much better match with actual human behaviour, including elements of morality such as honesty, responsibility and sincerity, as well as the more hostile aspects of human nature, such as anger and vengefulness. The mechanism at work here is commitment, which does not need population structure, nor does it need interactions to be repeated. We argue that this shift in focus can not only help explain why humans have evolved to know wrong from right, but also why other animals, with similar population structures and similar rates of repetition, have not evolved similar moral sentiments. The suggestion that the evolutionary function of morality is to help us commit to otherwise irrational behaviour stems from the work of Robert Frank (American Economic Review, 77(4), 593–604, 1987; Passions within reason: The strategic role of the emotions, WW Norton, 1988), which has played a surprisingly modest role in the scientific debate to date.https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/identifier/S2513843X21000360/type/journal_articleMoralitypro-socialitycommitmentultimatum gametrust gameinsurance gamepunishment
spellingShingle Aslihan Akdeniz
Matthijs van Veelen
The evolution of morality and the role of commitment
Evolutionary Human Sciences
Morality
pro-sociality
commitment
ultimatum game
trust game
insurance game
punishment
title The evolution of morality and the role of commitment
title_full The evolution of morality and the role of commitment
title_fullStr The evolution of morality and the role of commitment
title_full_unstemmed The evolution of morality and the role of commitment
title_short The evolution of morality and the role of commitment
title_sort evolution of morality and the role of commitment
topic Morality
pro-sociality
commitment
ultimatum game
trust game
insurance game
punishment
url https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/identifier/S2513843X21000360/type/journal_article
work_keys_str_mv AT aslihanakdeniz theevolutionofmoralityandtheroleofcommitment
AT matthijsvanveelen theevolutionofmoralityandtheroleofcommitment
AT aslihanakdeniz evolutionofmoralityandtheroleofcommitment
AT matthijsvanveelen evolutionofmoralityandtheroleofcommitment