Kant’s Four Political Conditions<subtitle>Barbarism, Anarchy, Despotism, and Republic</subtitle>

In Kant’s “Doctrine of Right” there is a philosophical and interpretive puzzle surrounding the translation of a key concept: Gewalt. Should we translate it as “force,” “power,” or “violence”? This raises both general questions in Kant’s legal-political philosophy as well as puzzles regarding Kant’s...

Full description

Bibliographic Details
Main Author: Helga Varden
Format: Article
Language:Norwegian Bokmål
Published: Scandinavian University Press/Universitetsforlaget 2022-09-01
Series:Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift
Subjects:
Online Access:http://www.idunn.no/doi/10.18261/nft.57.3-4.9
_version_ 1811209681449779200
author Helga Varden
author_facet Helga Varden
author_sort Helga Varden
collection DOAJ
description In Kant’s “Doctrine of Right” there is a philosophical and interpretive puzzle surrounding the translation of a key concept: Gewalt. Should we translate it as “force,” “power,” or “violence”? This raises both general questions in Kant’s legal-political philosophy as well as puzzles regarding Kant’s definitions of “barbarism,” “anarchy,” “despotism,” and “republic” as the four possible political conditions. First, I argue that we have good textual reasons for translating Gewalt as “violence”—a translation which has the advantage that it answers these questions and puzzles convincingly. Translating Gewalt as “violence” has two further, somewhat surprising advantages. It allows us to explain how human beings can be caught in situations with no morally good ways out, and it gives us an ideal Kantian refutation of the death penalty. I then explore Kant’s account of the establishment of public authorities by means of an analogy between the birth and development of a natural person (a human being) and an artificial one (a state). This analogy helps to clarify the difference between the necessary coercive element involved in ideally establishing a state and the likely violence involved in actually establishing one. The third and final section uses the ideas of barbarism, anarchy, despotism, and republic to identify four different types of political forces operating at any given time in actual historical societies. Once we use Kant’s theory to improve our understanding of the various challenges our historical societies present, we also realize the importance and usefulness of philosophical precision when we translate Gewalt as “violence” and correctly define barbarism, anarchy, despotism, and republic.
first_indexed 2024-04-12T04:43:30Z
format Article
id doaj.art-7b768e8df39f4dba99e61c6ddfd1a1f7
institution Directory Open Access Journal
issn 0029-1943
1504-2901
language Norwegian Bokmål
last_indexed 2024-04-12T04:43:30Z
publishDate 2022-09-01
publisher Scandinavian University Press/Universitetsforlaget
record_format Article
series Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift
spelling doaj.art-7b768e8df39f4dba99e61c6ddfd1a1f72022-12-22T03:47:33ZnobScandinavian University Press/UniversitetsforlagetNorsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift0029-19431504-29012022-09-01573-419420710.18261/nft.57.3-4.9Kant’s Four Political Conditions<subtitle>Barbarism, Anarchy, Despotism, and Republic</subtitle>Helga Varden0Professor, Professor in Philosophy, Women &amp; Women Studies, and Political Science, Department of Philosophy, University of Illinois at Urbana-ChampaignIn Kant’s “Doctrine of Right” there is a philosophical and interpretive puzzle surrounding the translation of a key concept: Gewalt. Should we translate it as “force,” “power,” or “violence”? This raises both general questions in Kant’s legal-political philosophy as well as puzzles regarding Kant’s definitions of “barbarism,” “anarchy,” “despotism,” and “republic” as the four possible political conditions. First, I argue that we have good textual reasons for translating Gewalt as “violence”—a translation which has the advantage that it answers these questions and puzzles convincingly. Translating Gewalt as “violence” has two further, somewhat surprising advantages. It allows us to explain how human beings can be caught in situations with no morally good ways out, and it gives us an ideal Kantian refutation of the death penalty. I then explore Kant’s account of the establishment of public authorities by means of an analogy between the birth and development of a natural person (a human being) and an artificial one (a state). This analogy helps to clarify the difference between the necessary coercive element involved in ideally establishing a state and the likely violence involved in actually establishing one. The third and final section uses the ideas of barbarism, anarchy, despotism, and republic to identify four different types of political forces operating at any given time in actual historical societies. Once we use Kant’s theory to improve our understanding of the various challenges our historical societies present, we also realize the importance and usefulness of philosophical precision when we translate Gewalt as “violence” and correctly define barbarism, anarchy, despotism, and republic.http://www.idunn.no/doi/10.18261/nft.57.3-4.9KantDoctrine of Rightdeath penaltybarbarismanarchydespotism
spellingShingle Helga Varden
Kant’s Four Political Conditions<subtitle>Barbarism, Anarchy, Despotism, and Republic</subtitle>
Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift
Kant
Doctrine of Right
death penalty
barbarism
anarchy
despotism
title Kant’s Four Political Conditions<subtitle>Barbarism, Anarchy, Despotism, and Republic</subtitle>
title_full Kant’s Four Political Conditions<subtitle>Barbarism, Anarchy, Despotism, and Republic</subtitle>
title_fullStr Kant’s Four Political Conditions<subtitle>Barbarism, Anarchy, Despotism, and Republic</subtitle>
title_full_unstemmed Kant’s Four Political Conditions<subtitle>Barbarism, Anarchy, Despotism, and Republic</subtitle>
title_short Kant’s Four Political Conditions<subtitle>Barbarism, Anarchy, Despotism, and Republic</subtitle>
title_sort kant s four political conditions subtitle barbarism anarchy despotism and republic subtitle
topic Kant
Doctrine of Right
death penalty
barbarism
anarchy
despotism
url http://www.idunn.no/doi/10.18261/nft.57.3-4.9
work_keys_str_mv AT helgavarden kantsfourpoliticalconditionssubtitlebarbarismanarchydespotismandrepublicsubtitle