Why Protagoras gets paid anyway: a practical solution of the paradox of court

The famous dispute between Protagoras and Euathlus concerning Protagoras’s tuition fee reportedly owed to him by Euathlus is solved on the basis of practical argumentation concerning actions. The dispute is widely viewed as a kind of a logical paradox, and I show that such treating arises due to the...

Full description

Bibliographic Details
Main Author: Elena Lisanyuk
Format: Article
Language:ell
Published: Novosibirsk State University Press 2017-01-01
Series:SCHOLE
Subjects:
Online Access:http://www.nsu.ru/classics/schole/11/11-1-lisanyuk.pdf
_version_ 1828087346813206528
author Elena Lisanyuk
author_facet Elena Lisanyuk
author_sort Elena Lisanyuk
collection DOAJ
description The famous dispute between Protagoras and Euathlus concerning Protagoras’s tuition fee reportedly owed to him by Euathlus is solved on the basis of practical argumentation concerning actions. The dispute is widely viewed as a kind of a logical paradox, and I show that such treating arises due to the double confusion in the dispute narrative. The linguistic expressions used to refer to Protagoras’s, Euathlus’s and the jurors’ actions are confused with these actions themselves. The other confusion is the collision between the pairs of incompatible actions ambiguously expressed by two different pairs of sentences, one of which is a propositionally consistent pair whereas the other is an inconsistent one. The actional (practical) paradox solution aims to clear up these confusions by means of two core borderlines, propositional and expressive, drawn between the actions and the propositions. The propositional distinction says that actions are empirical facts and they lack truth values unlike propositions, which are mental entities and are often employed for referring to the actions. This distinction helps to avoid the confusion between the empirical incompatibility of actions and the truth-functional inconsistency of propositions. The expressive distinction claims that although the same linguistic sentences can be used to refer both to actions and propositions, two empirically incompatible actions can be expressed both by a pair of inconsistent propositions as well as by a pair of consistent ones. Therefore, the action of Protagoras’s being paid may be linguistically symbolized in four different ways: Protagoras gets paid due to the verdict, Protagoras gets paid due to the contract that amount to Protagoras does not get paid by the contract and Protagoras does not get paid by the verdict respectively, and likewise for Euathlus’s actions. The two distinctions are used for classifying the two groups of paradox solutions, legal and logical, proposed so far depending on which of the two confusions they purport to escape from. The actional reconstruction of the paradox suggests that there is only one single agent in the dispute, Protagoras, while the other named Euathlus is a ‘phantom,’ which most probably was invented by Protagoras himself for the sake of creating this challenging sophism.
first_indexed 2024-04-11T05:10:56Z
format Article
id doaj.art-96408ddf2d7544609919051fccceeeb7
institution Directory Open Access Journal
issn 1995-4328
1995-4336
language ell
last_indexed 2024-04-11T05:10:56Z
publishDate 2017-01-01
publisher Novosibirsk State University Press
record_format Article
series SCHOLE
spelling doaj.art-96408ddf2d7544609919051fccceeeb72022-12-25T10:44:17ZellNovosibirsk State University PressSCHOLE1995-43281995-43362017-01-01111617710.21267/AQUILO.2017.11.4519Why Protagoras gets paid anyway: a practical solution of the paradox of courtElena Lisanyuk0St-Petersburg State UniversityThe famous dispute between Protagoras and Euathlus concerning Protagoras’s tuition fee reportedly owed to him by Euathlus is solved on the basis of practical argumentation concerning actions. The dispute is widely viewed as a kind of a logical paradox, and I show that such treating arises due to the double confusion in the dispute narrative. The linguistic expressions used to refer to Protagoras’s, Euathlus’s and the jurors’ actions are confused with these actions themselves. The other confusion is the collision between the pairs of incompatible actions ambiguously expressed by two different pairs of sentences, one of which is a propositionally consistent pair whereas the other is an inconsistent one. The actional (practical) paradox solution aims to clear up these confusions by means of two core borderlines, propositional and expressive, drawn between the actions and the propositions. The propositional distinction says that actions are empirical facts and they lack truth values unlike propositions, which are mental entities and are often employed for referring to the actions. This distinction helps to avoid the confusion between the empirical incompatibility of actions and the truth-functional inconsistency of propositions. The expressive distinction claims that although the same linguistic sentences can be used to refer both to actions and propositions, two empirically incompatible actions can be expressed both by a pair of inconsistent propositions as well as by a pair of consistent ones. Therefore, the action of Protagoras’s being paid may be linguistically symbolized in four different ways: Protagoras gets paid due to the verdict, Protagoras gets paid due to the contract that amount to Protagoras does not get paid by the contract and Protagoras does not get paid by the verdict respectively, and likewise for Euathlus’s actions. The two distinctions are used for classifying the two groups of paradox solutions, legal and logical, proposed so far depending on which of the two confusions they purport to escape from. The actional reconstruction of the paradox suggests that there is only one single agent in the dispute, Protagoras, while the other named Euathlus is a ‘phantom,’ which most probably was invented by Protagoras himself for the sake of creating this challenging sophism.http://www.nsu.ru/classics/schole/11/11-1-lisanyuk.pdfProtagoraslogical paradoxargumentationagencyactionsophism
spellingShingle Elena Lisanyuk
Why Protagoras gets paid anyway: a practical solution of the paradox of court
SCHOLE
Protagoras
logical paradox
argumentation
agency
action
sophism
title Why Protagoras gets paid anyway: a practical solution of the paradox of court
title_full Why Protagoras gets paid anyway: a practical solution of the paradox of court
title_fullStr Why Protagoras gets paid anyway: a practical solution of the paradox of court
title_full_unstemmed Why Protagoras gets paid anyway: a practical solution of the paradox of court
title_short Why Protagoras gets paid anyway: a practical solution of the paradox of court
title_sort why protagoras gets paid anyway a practical solution of the paradox of court
topic Protagoras
logical paradox
argumentation
agency
action
sophism
url http://www.nsu.ru/classics/schole/11/11-1-lisanyuk.pdf
work_keys_str_mv AT elenalisanyuk whyprotagorasgetspaidanywayapracticalsolutionoftheparadoxofcourt