Ideals of Inclusion in Deliberation

Building on prior thinking about political representation in democratic deliberation, we argue for four ideals of inclusion, each of which is most appropriate to a different situation. These principles of inclusion depend not only on the goals of a deliberation, but also on its level of empowerment...

Full description

Bibliographic Details
Main Authors: Chad Raphael, Christopher F. Karpowitz
Format: Article
Language:English
Published: University of Westminster Press 2016-10-01
Series:Journal of Deliberative Democracy
Subjects:
Online Access:https://delibdemjournal.org/article/id/527/
_version_ 1811309559928586240
author Chad Raphael
Christopher F. Karpowitz
author_facet Chad Raphael
Christopher F. Karpowitz
author_sort Chad Raphael
collection DOAJ
description Building on prior thinking about political representation in democratic deliberation, we argue for four ideals of inclusion, each of which is most appropriate to a different situation. These principles of inclusion depend not only on the goals of a deliberation, but also on its level of empowerment in the political system, and its openness to all who want to participate. Holistic and open deliberations can most legitimately incorporate and decide for the people as a whole if they are open to all who want to participate and affirmatively recruit perspectives that would be underrepresented otherwise. Chicago Community Policing beat meetings offer an example. Holistic and restricted forums (such as the latter stages of some participatory budgeting processes) should recruit stratified random samples of the demos, but must also ensure that problems of tokenism are overcome by including a critical mass of the least powerful perspectives, so that their views can be aired and heard more fully and effectively. Forums that aim to improve relations between social sectors and peoples should provide open access for all who are affected by the issues (relational and open), if possible, or recruit a stratified random sample of all affected, when necessary (relational and restricted). In either case, proportional representation of the least advantaged perspectives is necessary. However, when deliberation focuses on relations between a disempowered group and the rest of society, or between unequal peoples, it is often most legitimate to over-sample the least powerful and even to create opportunities for the disempowered to deliberate among themselves so that their perspectives can be adequately represented in small and large group discussions. We illustrate this discussion with examples of atypical Deliberative Polls on Australia’s reconciliation with its indigenous community and the Roma ethnic minority in Europe.
first_indexed 2024-04-13T09:44:04Z
format Article
id doaj.art-b5c42acbf5b64f328b3e7b0c90f59602
institution Directory Open Access Journal
issn 2634-0488
language English
last_indexed 2024-04-13T09:44:04Z
publishDate 2016-10-01
publisher University of Westminster Press
record_format Article
series Journal of Deliberative Democracy
spelling doaj.art-b5c42acbf5b64f328b3e7b0c90f596022022-12-22T02:51:49ZengUniversity of Westminster PressJournal of Deliberative Democracy2634-04882016-10-0112210.16997/jdd.255Ideals of Inclusion in DeliberationChad Raphael0Christopher F. Karpowitz1 Building on prior thinking about political representation in democratic deliberation, we argue for four ideals of inclusion, each of which is most appropriate to a different situation. These principles of inclusion depend not only on the goals of a deliberation, but also on its level of empowerment in the political system, and its openness to all who want to participate. Holistic and open deliberations can most legitimately incorporate and decide for the people as a whole if they are open to all who want to participate and affirmatively recruit perspectives that would be underrepresented otherwise. Chicago Community Policing beat meetings offer an example. Holistic and restricted forums (such as the latter stages of some participatory budgeting processes) should recruit stratified random samples of the demos, but must also ensure that problems of tokenism are overcome by including a critical mass of the least powerful perspectives, so that their views can be aired and heard more fully and effectively. Forums that aim to improve relations between social sectors and peoples should provide open access for all who are affected by the issues (relational and open), if possible, or recruit a stratified random sample of all affected, when necessary (relational and restricted). In either case, proportional representation of the least advantaged perspectives is necessary. However, when deliberation focuses on relations between a disempowered group and the rest of society, or between unequal peoples, it is often most legitimate to over-sample the least powerful and even to create opportunities for the disempowered to deliberate among themselves so that their perspectives can be adequately represented in small and large group discussions. We illustrate this discussion with examples of atypical Deliberative Polls on Australia’s reconciliation with its indigenous community and the Roma ethnic minority in Europe.https://delibdemjournal.org/article/id/527/equalityequityrepresentationinclusion
spellingShingle Chad Raphael
Christopher F. Karpowitz
Ideals of Inclusion in Deliberation
Journal of Deliberative Democracy
equality
equity
representation
inclusion
title Ideals of Inclusion in Deliberation
title_full Ideals of Inclusion in Deliberation
title_fullStr Ideals of Inclusion in Deliberation
title_full_unstemmed Ideals of Inclusion in Deliberation
title_short Ideals of Inclusion in Deliberation
title_sort ideals of inclusion in deliberation
topic equality
equity
representation
inclusion
url https://delibdemjournal.org/article/id/527/
work_keys_str_mv AT chadraphael idealsofinclusionindeliberation
AT christopherfkarpowitz idealsofinclusionindeliberation