Communication and deniability: Moral and epistemic reactions to denials

People often deny having meant what the audience understood. Such denials occur in both interpersonal and institutional contexts, such as in political discourse, the interpretation of laws and the perception of lies. In practice, denials have a wide range of possible effects on the audience, such as...

Full description

Bibliographic Details
Main Authors: Francesca Bonalumi, Feride Belma Bumin, Thom Scott-Phillips, Christophe Heintz
Format: Article
Language:English
Published: Frontiers Media S.A. 2023-01-01
Series:Frontiers in Psychology
Subjects:
Online Access:https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2022.1073213/full
_version_ 1797962027687215104
author Francesca Bonalumi
Feride Belma Bumin
Thom Scott-Phillips
Christophe Heintz
author_facet Francesca Bonalumi
Feride Belma Bumin
Thom Scott-Phillips
Christophe Heintz
author_sort Francesca Bonalumi
collection DOAJ
description People often deny having meant what the audience understood. Such denials occur in both interpersonal and institutional contexts, such as in political discourse, the interpretation of laws and the perception of lies. In practice, denials have a wide range of possible effects on the audience, such as conversational repair, reinterpretation of the original utterance, moral judgements about the speaker, and rejection of the denial. When are these different reactions triggered? What factors make denials credible? There are surprisingly few experimental studies directly targeting such questions. Here, we present two pre-registered experiments focusing on (i) the speaker’s incentives to mislead their audience, and (ii) the impact of speaker denials on audiences’ moral and epistemic assessments of what has been said. We find that the extent to which speakers are judged responsible for the audience’s interpretations is modulated by their (the speakers’) incentives to mislead, but not by denials themselves. We also find that people are more willing than we expected to revise their interpretation of the speaker’s utterance when they learn that the ascribed meaning is false, regardless of whether the speaker is known to have had incentives to deceive their audience. In general, these findings are consistent with the idea that communicators are held responsible for the cognitive effects they trigger in their audience; rather than being responsible for, more narrowly, only the effects of what was “literally” said. In light of our findings, we present a new, cognitive analysis of how audiences react to denials, drawing in particular on the Relevance Theory approach to communication. We distinguish in particular: (a) the spontaneous and intuitive re-interpretation of the original utterance in light of a denial; (b) the attribution of responsibility to the speaker for the cognitive effects of what is communicated; and (c) the reflective attribution of a particular intention to the speaker, which include argumentative considerations, higher-order deniability, and reputational concerns. Existing experimental work, including our own, aims mostly at (a) and (b), and does not adequately control for (c). Deeper understanding of what can be credibly denied will be hindered unless and until this methodological problem is resolved.
first_indexed 2024-04-11T01:06:52Z
format Article
id doaj.art-c9e15c2facd64ab8aa6decda847d62ef
institution Directory Open Access Journal
issn 1664-1078
language English
last_indexed 2024-04-11T01:06:52Z
publishDate 2023-01-01
publisher Frontiers Media S.A.
record_format Article
series Frontiers in Psychology
spelling doaj.art-c9e15c2facd64ab8aa6decda847d62ef2023-01-04T12:04:03ZengFrontiers Media S.A.Frontiers in Psychology1664-10782023-01-011310.3389/fpsyg.2022.10732131073213Communication and deniability: Moral and epistemic reactions to denialsFrancesca Bonalumi0Feride Belma Bumin1Thom Scott-Phillips2Christophe Heintz3Department of Cognitive Science, Central European University, Vienna, AustriaDepartment of Economics and Business, Central European University, Vienna, AustriaInstitute for Logic Cognition Language and Information, University of the Basque Country, San Sebastian, SpainDepartment of Cognitive Science, Central European University, Vienna, AustriaPeople often deny having meant what the audience understood. Such denials occur in both interpersonal and institutional contexts, such as in political discourse, the interpretation of laws and the perception of lies. In practice, denials have a wide range of possible effects on the audience, such as conversational repair, reinterpretation of the original utterance, moral judgements about the speaker, and rejection of the denial. When are these different reactions triggered? What factors make denials credible? There are surprisingly few experimental studies directly targeting such questions. Here, we present two pre-registered experiments focusing on (i) the speaker’s incentives to mislead their audience, and (ii) the impact of speaker denials on audiences’ moral and epistemic assessments of what has been said. We find that the extent to which speakers are judged responsible for the audience’s interpretations is modulated by their (the speakers’) incentives to mislead, but not by denials themselves. We also find that people are more willing than we expected to revise their interpretation of the speaker’s utterance when they learn that the ascribed meaning is false, regardless of whether the speaker is known to have had incentives to deceive their audience. In general, these findings are consistent with the idea that communicators are held responsible for the cognitive effects they trigger in their audience; rather than being responsible for, more narrowly, only the effects of what was “literally” said. In light of our findings, we present a new, cognitive analysis of how audiences react to denials, drawing in particular on the Relevance Theory approach to communication. We distinguish in particular: (a) the spontaneous and intuitive re-interpretation of the original utterance in light of a denial; (b) the attribution of responsibility to the speaker for the cognitive effects of what is communicated; and (c) the reflective attribution of a particular intention to the speaker, which include argumentative considerations, higher-order deniability, and reputational concerns. Existing experimental work, including our own, aims mostly at (a) and (b), and does not adequately control for (c). Deeper understanding of what can be credibly denied will be hindered unless and until this methodological problem is resolved.https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2022.1073213/fulldeniabilityRelevance Theorystrategic speakerindirect communicationpragmaticsaccountability
spellingShingle Francesca Bonalumi
Feride Belma Bumin
Thom Scott-Phillips
Christophe Heintz
Communication and deniability: Moral and epistemic reactions to denials
Frontiers in Psychology
deniability
Relevance Theory
strategic speaker
indirect communication
pragmatics
accountability
title Communication and deniability: Moral and epistemic reactions to denials
title_full Communication and deniability: Moral and epistemic reactions to denials
title_fullStr Communication and deniability: Moral and epistemic reactions to denials
title_full_unstemmed Communication and deniability: Moral and epistemic reactions to denials
title_short Communication and deniability: Moral and epistemic reactions to denials
title_sort communication and deniability moral and epistemic reactions to denials
topic deniability
Relevance Theory
strategic speaker
indirect communication
pragmatics
accountability
url https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2022.1073213/full
work_keys_str_mv AT francescabonalumi communicationanddeniabilitymoralandepistemicreactionstodenials
AT feridebelmabumin communicationanddeniabilitymoralandepistemicreactionstodenials
AT thomscottphillips communicationanddeniabilitymoralandepistemicreactionstodenials
AT christopheheintz communicationanddeniabilitymoralandepistemicreactionstodenials