The Comparative Psychology of Intelligence: Some Thirty Years Later

After re-reading Macphail’s (1987) essay “The Comparative Psychology of Intelligence” with all the associated commentaries, I was struck by how contemporary many of the arguments and counter-arguments still appear. Of course, we now know much more about the abilities of many more species (including...

Ausführliche Beschreibung

Bibliographische Detailangaben
1. Verfasser: Pepperberg, Irene M
Weitere Verfasser: Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Media Laboratory
Format: Artikel
Sprache:English
Veröffentlicht: Frontiers Media SA 2020
Online Zugang:https://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/128387
_version_ 1826215045957156864
author Pepperberg, Irene M
author2 Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Media Laboratory
author_facet Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Media Laboratory
Pepperberg, Irene M
author_sort Pepperberg, Irene M
collection MIT
description After re-reading Macphail’s (1987) essay “The Comparative Psychology of Intelligence” with all the associated commentaries, I was struck by how contemporary many of the arguments and counter-arguments still appear. Of course, we now know much more about the abilities of many more species (including their neurobiology) and fewer researchers currently favor explanations of behavior based solely on associative processes; however, the role of contextual variables in comparative psychology still remains cloudy. I discuss these issues briefly. Given my research interests involving the cognitive and communicative abilities of Grey parrots, the one aspect of the original article upon which I feel I can comment in depth involves Macphail’s claims about the importance of language—and specifically syntax—in problem-solving and thus in placing humans above all other creatures. Granted, no other species has (or in my opinion is likely ever to acquire) everything that goes into what is considered “human language.” Nevertheless, several other species have acquired symbolic representation, and considerable information now exists upon which to base an argument that such acquisition by itself enables more complex and “human-like” cognitive processes. Such processes may form the basis of the kind of intelligence that is measured—not surprisingly—with human-based tasks, including the use of such representations as a means to directly query non-human subjects in ways not unlike those used with young children.
first_indexed 2024-09-23T16:15:59Z
format Article
id mit-1721.1/128387
institution Massachusetts Institute of Technology
language English
last_indexed 2024-09-23T16:15:59Z
publishDate 2020
publisher Frontiers Media SA
record_format dspace
spelling mit-1721.1/1283872022-09-29T19:14:39Z The Comparative Psychology of Intelligence: Some Thirty Years Later Pepperberg, Irene M Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Media Laboratory Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Department of Brain and Cognitive Sciences After re-reading Macphail’s (1987) essay “The Comparative Psychology of Intelligence” with all the associated commentaries, I was struck by how contemporary many of the arguments and counter-arguments still appear. Of course, we now know much more about the abilities of many more species (including their neurobiology) and fewer researchers currently favor explanations of behavior based solely on associative processes; however, the role of contextual variables in comparative psychology still remains cloudy. I discuss these issues briefly. Given my research interests involving the cognitive and communicative abilities of Grey parrots, the one aspect of the original article upon which I feel I can comment in depth involves Macphail’s claims about the importance of language—and specifically syntax—in problem-solving and thus in placing humans above all other creatures. Granted, no other species has (or in my opinion is likely ever to acquire) everything that goes into what is considered “human language.” Nevertheless, several other species have acquired symbolic representation, and considerable information now exists upon which to base an argument that such acquisition by itself enables more complex and “human-like” cognitive processes. Such processes may form the basis of the kind of intelligence that is measured—not surprisingly—with human-based tasks, including the use of such representations as a means to directly query non-human subjects in ways not unlike those used with young children. 2020-11-06T18:52:29Z 2020-11-06T18:52:29Z 2020-05 2020-01 2020-10-19T12:45:03Z Article http://purl.org/eprint/type/JournalArticle 1664-1078 https://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/128387 Pepperberg, Irene M. "The Comparative Psychology of Intelligence: Some Thirty Years Later." Frontiers in Psychology 11 (May 2020): 973 © 2020 Pepperberg en http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.00973 Frontiers in Psychology Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International license https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ application/pdf Frontiers Media SA Frontiers
spellingShingle Pepperberg, Irene M
The Comparative Psychology of Intelligence: Some Thirty Years Later
title The Comparative Psychology of Intelligence: Some Thirty Years Later
title_full The Comparative Psychology of Intelligence: Some Thirty Years Later
title_fullStr The Comparative Psychology of Intelligence: Some Thirty Years Later
title_full_unstemmed The Comparative Psychology of Intelligence: Some Thirty Years Later
title_short The Comparative Psychology of Intelligence: Some Thirty Years Later
title_sort comparative psychology of intelligence some thirty years later
url https://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/128387
work_keys_str_mv AT pepperbergirenem thecomparativepsychologyofintelligencesomethirtyyearslater
AT pepperbergirenem comparativepsychologyofintelligencesomethirtyyearslater