Religious political arguments, accessibility, and democratic deliberation

Christian critics of liberalism, and especially of contemporary public-reason liberalism, often argue that it objectionably excludes religious voices form the public square, by requiring citizens to bracket their religious convictions when they engage in democratic deliberation. In response, libera...

Celý popis

Podrobná bibliografie
Hlavní autor: Billingham, P
Médium: Journal article
Jazyk:English
Vydáno: Notre Dame Law School 2023
_version_ 1826310167353884672
author Billingham, P
author_facet Billingham, P
author_sort Billingham, P
collection OXFORD
description Christian critics of liberalism, and especially of contemporary public-reason liberalism, often argue that it objectionably excludes religious voices form the public square, by requiring citizens to bracket their religious convictions when they engage in democratic deliberation. In response, liberals often deny that their views have this implication. Many public-reason liberal theorists are “inclusivists,” who permit religious contributions to deliberation. <br> Yet even inclusivists provide little reason to think that religious political arguments can be persuasive or fruitful. After all, they tend to see religious reasons as inaccessible to others, due to relying on beliefs, values, and methods of reasoning that others do not share. Other citizens are seemingly unable to assess their validity, critically engage with them, or be persuaded by them. <br> This Article challenges this view. It seeks to show that other citizens can meaningfully engage with religious political arguments, such that those arguments can play a productive and persuasive role within public deliberation and in ways that can ultimately shape the content of laws. All of this can be true even if religious arguments do not meet the standard of accessibility required to qualify as public reasons. To make this case, I discuss two arguments from Christian theologians. <br> The Article speaks to two audiences. First, it shows that liberals (including public-reason liberals) should positively welcome religious arguments within democratic deliberation. Liberalism, on its own terms, should be more open to religious reasoning than is commonly assumed. Second, this shows that Christian critics of liberalism can be answered, on this point at least.
first_indexed 2024-03-07T07:46:34Z
format Journal article
id oxford-uuid:2d42e0a4-2358-4f63-b978-aa19521c15f1
institution University of Oxford
language English
last_indexed 2024-03-07T07:46:34Z
publishDate 2023
publisher Notre Dame Law School
record_format dspace
spelling oxford-uuid:2d42e0a4-2358-4f63-b978-aa19521c15f12023-06-20T10:23:34ZReligious political arguments, accessibility, and democratic deliberationJournal articlehttp://purl.org/coar/resource_type/c_dcae04bcuuid:2d42e0a4-2358-4f63-b978-aa19521c15f1EnglishSymplectic ElementsNotre Dame Law School2023Billingham, PChristian critics of liberalism, and especially of contemporary public-reason liberalism, often argue that it objectionably excludes religious voices form the public square, by requiring citizens to bracket their religious convictions when they engage in democratic deliberation. In response, liberals often deny that their views have this implication. Many public-reason liberal theorists are “inclusivists,” who permit religious contributions to deliberation. <br> Yet even inclusivists provide little reason to think that religious political arguments can be persuasive or fruitful. After all, they tend to see religious reasons as inaccessible to others, due to relying on beliefs, values, and methods of reasoning that others do not share. Other citizens are seemingly unable to assess their validity, critically engage with them, or be persuaded by them. <br> This Article challenges this view. It seeks to show that other citizens can meaningfully engage with religious political arguments, such that those arguments can play a productive and persuasive role within public deliberation and in ways that can ultimately shape the content of laws. All of this can be true even if religious arguments do not meet the standard of accessibility required to qualify as public reasons. To make this case, I discuss two arguments from Christian theologians. <br> The Article speaks to two audiences. First, it shows that liberals (including public-reason liberals) should positively welcome religious arguments within democratic deliberation. Liberalism, on its own terms, should be more open to religious reasoning than is commonly assumed. Second, this shows that Christian critics of liberalism can be answered, on this point at least.
spellingShingle Billingham, P
Religious political arguments, accessibility, and democratic deliberation
title Religious political arguments, accessibility, and democratic deliberation
title_full Religious political arguments, accessibility, and democratic deliberation
title_fullStr Religious political arguments, accessibility, and democratic deliberation
title_full_unstemmed Religious political arguments, accessibility, and democratic deliberation
title_short Religious political arguments, accessibility, and democratic deliberation
title_sort religious political arguments accessibility and democratic deliberation
work_keys_str_mv AT billinghamp religiouspoliticalargumentsaccessibilityanddemocraticdeliberation