Hume's pivotal argument, and his supposed obligation of reason
Treatise 1.4.1 argues that whenever we assess our probability of error, “we are oblig’d by our reason” to consider also the probability of error in that assessment, leading to a fatal regress which—but for irresistible nature—would extinguish all belief. The argument plays a huge role in the Treatis...
Главный автор: | |
---|---|
Формат: | Journal article |
Язык: | English |
Опубликовано: |
Duke University Press
2018
|
_version_ | 1826310102655696896 |
---|---|
author | Millican, P |
author_facet | Millican, P |
author_sort | Millican, P |
collection | OXFORD |
description | Treatise 1.4.1 argues that whenever we assess our probability of error, “we are oblig’d by our reason” to consider also the probability of error in that assessment, leading to a fatal regress which—but for irresistible nature—would extinguish all belief. The argument plays a huge role in the Treatise, and has recently attracted many defenders, rejecting the previously standard objection that iterated reflection need not imply reduction of probability. This paper, however, presses a more fundamental objection—that there is no obligation of reason to iterate in the first place—something obscured by the failure of previous analyses to focus on specific examples. Unlike the Treatise, Hume’s Enquiry of 1748 is richly illustrated with examples, making it likely that he himself would have encountered these problems. And there are traces in the Enquiry of a fundamental change of view, corroborating the significance of this argument for his philosophical development. |
first_indexed | 2024-03-07T07:47:13Z |
format | Journal article |
id | oxford-uuid:9a2a88a5-e3a6-432b-9bf8-fd5add50a65f |
institution | University of Oxford |
language | English |
last_indexed | 2024-03-07T07:47:13Z |
publishDate | 2018 |
publisher | Duke University Press |
record_format | dspace |
spelling | oxford-uuid:9a2a88a5-e3a6-432b-9bf8-fd5add50a65f2023-06-12T14:50:59ZHume's pivotal argument, and his supposed obligation of reasonJournal articlehttp://purl.org/coar/resource_type/c_dcae04bcuuid:9a2a88a5-e3a6-432b-9bf8-fd5add50a65fEnglishSymplectic ElementsDuke University Press2018Millican, PTreatise 1.4.1 argues that whenever we assess our probability of error, “we are oblig’d by our reason” to consider also the probability of error in that assessment, leading to a fatal regress which—but for irresistible nature—would extinguish all belief. The argument plays a huge role in the Treatise, and has recently attracted many defenders, rejecting the previously standard objection that iterated reflection need not imply reduction of probability. This paper, however, presses a more fundamental objection—that there is no obligation of reason to iterate in the first place—something obscured by the failure of previous analyses to focus on specific examples. Unlike the Treatise, Hume’s Enquiry of 1748 is richly illustrated with examples, making it likely that he himself would have encountered these problems. And there are traces in the Enquiry of a fundamental change of view, corroborating the significance of this argument for his philosophical development. |
spellingShingle | Millican, P Hume's pivotal argument, and his supposed obligation of reason |
title | Hume's pivotal argument, and his supposed obligation of reason |
title_full | Hume's pivotal argument, and his supposed obligation of reason |
title_fullStr | Hume's pivotal argument, and his supposed obligation of reason |
title_full_unstemmed | Hume's pivotal argument, and his supposed obligation of reason |
title_short | Hume's pivotal argument, and his supposed obligation of reason |
title_sort | hume s pivotal argument and his supposed obligation of reason |
work_keys_str_mv | AT millicanp humespivotalargumentandhissupposedobligationofreason |